The ontological argument is an argument for the existence of God. It goes something like this.
- God is that which no greater can be conceived
- It is greater to exist in reality than in idea alone
- Therefore, God cannot simply exist in our heads, because a God that actually exists is greater than a God that doesn't actually exist
I've always felt that this is a completely sound argument for the existence of an ultimate entity. Entities seem to exist on a spectrum, and there must be something at the ends of either spectrum. Be it free-floating amino acids on one end, and some sort of galactic intelligence on the other. But the argument says nothing about the ultimate intelligence, only that it must be there.
That's my take on it, but regardless of any novel interpretation, the argument is not widely supported. Alvin Plantinga is perhaps the most notable proponent of the argument, and being a logician, he's applied what he knows to the argument and created a modal ontological argument.
Modal logic deals with possibility. E.g. it is possible that "A". But the corollary to possibility is necessity. It is necessary that "A". Modal logic also uses as the core of its thought a concept that's getting a lot of play recently, what with string theory and all that: possible worlds. Anything that is possible is actually happening in different realms of existence. There is a world where I am the king of England and another in which I died at birth. If it's logically possible, it exists.
Thus, something is possible if it exists in at least one possible world. It is necessary if it exists in all possible worlds. And it is contingent if it exists in some possible worlds.
Using these concepts called modal operators, Plantinga sets out to argue for the existence of God. I find the entire argument to be, like everything else in the philosophy of religion, to be circular; a giant, begged question.
I stole this specifically from here.
(1) If God exists then he has necessary existence.
(2) Either God has necessary existence, or he doesn’t.
(3) If God doesn’t have necessary existence, then he necessarily doesn’t.
Therefore:
(4) Either God has necessary existence, or he necessarily doesn’t.
(5) If God necessarily doesn’t have necessary existence, then God necessarily doesn’t exist.
Therefore:
(6) Either God has necessary existence, or he necessarily doesn’t exist.
(7) It is not the case that God necessarily doesn’t exist.
Therefore:
(8) God has necessary existence.
(9) If God has necessary existence, then God exists.
Therefore:
(10) God exists.
Premise 2 is a restatement of premise one. And premise 3 adds nothing. It's a rejiggering of "either God as we conceive of him exists or he doesn't."
1. If god exists, then he has necessary existence.
- Basically Iff (if and only if) G (God exists), then N (he is necessary)
- Which is G = N
- If God exists, then God exists.
- Oh yeah. There's a masterpiece of logic.
2. Either God has necessary existence or he doesn’t.
- Basically, either God exists or he doesn’t exist, because if he exists, he has necessary existence.
- This is the first part where the usage of existence jumps around. He both exists and has existence as though it's a property.
3. If God doesn’t have necessary existence, then he necessarily doesn’t.
- Once again, semantic dodge. If God doesn’t exist, then he doesn’t.
4. Either God has necessary existence, or he necessarily doesn’t.
- Either God exists or he doesn’t exist.
5. If God necessarily doesn’t have necessary existence, then God necessarily doesn’t exist.
- If God necessarily doesn’t exist, then he doesn’t exist.
6. Either God has necessary existence, or he necessarily doesn’t exist.
- Either he necessarily exists or necessarily doesn’t exist.
7. It is not the case that God necessarily doesn’t exist.
- It was dealing with possibility earlier on to reach this point. IF God doesn’t exist, then he necessarily doesn’t exist. The first “if” is not answered. Only IF God exists, does he exist. Only IF God exists, does he not necessarily not exist. And ONLY IF God doesn't exist, does he necessarily not exist.
8. God has necessary existence.
- He only has necessary existence if he exists, which has not been determined
9. If God has necessary existence, then God exists.
10. Therefore, God exists.
My slight re-wording of the argument might seem like I'm playing with words to achieve my goal, and I am. But that's because the argument is playing the same damned game. The argument jumps back and forth between existence as a property or a state and conveniently forgets that the actual question is never answered.
No comments:
Post a Comment